Beauty, Meaning, and the Art Establishment:
A Comparison of Hickey and Foucault
“Beauty”—it is hard to imagine that such a simple, commonplace
word so inherently tied to art could cause uproar in the very community in which
it is used. But this was exactly the case when then-unknown critic Dave Hickey
came out with “The Invisible Dragon,” a collection of critical essays
on beauty and the art establishment. Turning the word against the art institutions
of today, Hickey lamented the loss of the viewer’s individual perception
of aesthetics to the universal necessity of a deeper artistic meaning dictated
by the most prominent people in the art world. This bold statement caused controversy,
for it went against everything art had gained through the discussions of the
artistically-educated and well-known philosophers on the constituents of good
art. It could be said that the writings of one philosopher in particular, Michael
Foucault, were especially at stake, as his arguments on the importance of meaning
to art in The Order of Things are on the surface, completely contradicting Hickey’s
rants for a return to aesthetic appreciation. However, further analysis of the
two viewpoints leads to a surprising potential—that perhaps the opinions
of Hickey and Foucault are not so far off in their attempts to change the dynamics
of the art scene as a social institution.
Hickey’s argument against the denouncement of beauty in today’s
art world begins with the role of beauty. Truly, his argument can be boiled
down to the much-used phrase “beauty is in the eye of the beholder.”
He fervently affirms that beauty allows for a personal, one-on-one experience
with the piece of art, and is the sole component that allows for the viewer
to create their own, individual thoughts on the piece. Hickey goes on to say
that it is the central theory for art criticism, for the pleasure derived from
viewing a beautiful artwork is “the only true occasion for looking at
anything” and it is beauty alone that allows for the measurement of a
piece’s efficacy (Hickey 2). Thus, beauty can be deemed more important
than meaning in artwork because it allows the viewer an unadulterated measure
of worth.
Foucault, on the other hand, demonstrates the importance of meaning in the first
chapter of his essay, The Order of Things. This he accomplishes through a thorough
analysis of Diego Velázquez’s painting, “Las Meninas,”
using the aesthetic components of the work to argue the true focus of the painting
and its significance (Fig. A). It becomes clear to Foucault, then, that the
focus of the painting, through the suggested lines of the painting and the gazes
of the subjects, is the viewer: “As soon as they place the spectator in
the field of their gaze, the painter’s eyes seize hold of him, force him
to enter the picture, assign him a place at once privileged and inescapable…,
and project it upon the inaccessible surface of the canvas within the picture”
(Foucault 444). The significance of this aspect is revealed when one realizes
the context in which the painting was created. Classical representation dominated
the art scene in Velázquez’s time, and was characterized by the
concept of “imitation of nature,” i.e., the representation of objects
that existed in the real world outside the artist’s mind (Bate). However,
Velázquez begins to break the mold by incorporating the mystery and potential
of an invisible viewer as the subject on a concealed canvas, invoking a change
in the art world that helped to alter its direction. Through this determination,
Foucault implies that it is meaning that is essential to the experience and
importance of a piece of art.
However, while Hickey and Foucault appear superficially to embody different
viewpoints on art, their perspectives, when taken further, seem to in fact address
a similar issue. Deeper than simple aesthetics and meaning, this problem permeates
the art world, the ability to obtain an effective artistic experience and the
advancement of art. Hickey argues that this issue is embodied in the deterioration
of beauty’s role in art experience today. As a main component of art,
the beauty Hickey finds to be essential has become obsolete in today’s
art world because of the development of what he terms the “therapeutic
institution.” This concept is essentially representative of the change
in value in the art world from merit-based to a political agenda of governmental,
corporate and academic entities. Beauty, an entirely inherent concept, was seen
by this “art establishment”—museum owners, critics, the art-educated,
funders, etc.—as that which sells art, no matter the influence on it by
the establishment. To keep a hold on the art world, the institution brought
art into the public sector, feeding the community its qualified opinion that
it is meaning which qualifies art as legitimate and beauty which lessens the
quality of art. Thus, they essentially gave themselves the upper hand over the
general public art-wise with an exclusive thought process, a notion trucker
Terri Horton found especially frustrating through repeated denials by the elite
art establishment to verify her “Jackson Pollock” (Fig. B). The
result of this manipulation, Hickey argues with Horton-esque passion, is a fraud
of an art world, a product of the therapeutic institution telling us what to
think is “good” art.
To illustrate this corruption further, Hickey actually uses a Foucault-inspired
comparison of “bureaucratic surveillance and autocratic punishment”
(Hickey 5). Foucault’s logic is that a king, in his demand for certain
constants like loyalty, has a cruel but justified punishment for deviation that
at least lets the deviant retain his convictions (Hickey 5). Bureaucratic rule,
on the other hand, uses its regulatory policies as guidelines that seep unknowingly
into the public consciousness, conforming it to its wishes and taking its freedom
of interpretation. To Hickey, this Foucaultian logic is a clear illustration
of the therapeutic institution’s subconscious attack on public appreciation
of beauty and an argument against the art establishment.
Foucaultian concepts again lend themselves to the argument against Hickey’s
therapeutic institution in the preface of The Order of Things. It is here that
Foucault makes his argument for the necessity of a change in the order of a
culture for its advancement. He establishes that every culture has “fundamental
codes” that govern “its language, its schemas of perception, its
exchanges, its techniques, its values, [and] its hierarchy of perception”
(Foucault 440). This empirical “order” dictates how people act until
a proposed discourse brings forth the construction of a new order, making the
old obsolete. It is through this questioning and reasoning that new knowledge
is acquired and the culture grows. This is what Foucault demonstrates through
“Las Meninas,” that Velázquez’s bold and innovative
changes to representation lead to changes in the perception and “rules”
of the art world that ultimately bring art theory to where it is today. However,
the therapeutic institution of which Hickey speaks threatens discourse on and
thus growth of the art community present today. Without the ability to judge
art on its beauty regardless of any intended meaning, art as we know it today
stays stuck in a rut dictated by so-called art professionals. Thus Foucault’s
argumentation solidifies Hickey’s viewpoints on the pitfalls of the current
art establishment.
Foucault and Hickey, though coming from different perspectives, work together
to raise important criticisms of the art world today. However, what does this
ultimately gain for the viewer and the artist? While still under the influence
of the therapeutic institution, both are slaves to a narrow, adulterated interpretation
of art. Without the ability of an individual experience and uninhibited creation
and critique, the art culture is not moving anywhere fast. Nevertheless, Hickey
maintains that the “vernacular of beauty” used by effective artists
like Warhol will overcome, engaging individuals “in arguments about what
is good and beautiful” (Hickey 17). Perhaps the strides made by Hickey
and Foucault will bring the culture of art into a time when Warhols can be appreciated
for their shocking aesthetics and their nonchalant artistic commentary, a time
when art can be art as a meshing of pleasure, meaning, and individual interpretation
free of the art establishment.
Works Cited
Bate,
Walter Jackson. “Prefaces to Criticism.” Ourcivilization.com. 27
April 2009. A Theory of
Civilization. <http://www.ourcivilisation.com/smartboard/shop/batewj/class.htm>.
Foucault, Michael. “The Order of Things.” Art and its Significance:
An Anthology of Aesthetic
Theory. Ed. Stephen David Ross. Albany: State University of New York Press,
1994. 440-454.
Hickey, Dave. “The Invisible Dragon: Essays on Beauty.” Chicago:
The University of Chicago
Press, 2009.
Attachments:
Figure A. “Las Meninas”
by Diego Velázquez
(http://www.artchive.com/artchive/V/velazquez/meninas.jpg.html)
Figure B. Terri Horton’s
Jackson Pollock painting
(http://www.nytimes.com/2006/11/09/arts/design/09poll.html)
==================================
Ann Reves:
I have always really enjoyed drawing but never took an analytical perspective on art. It’s usually a little hard for me to look at things from a philosophical standpoint as a Biology/Pre-PT major, and writing is not my favorite thing to do in the world, but I was inspired by the well-written arguments of Hickey and Foucault to write this comparative analysis of their standpoints on art. I found it interesting that both, in one way or another, critiqued the direction in which the art institution is going today.