Good Art: Taste or Instinct?
Is human behavior innately
in our genes or acquired through socialization, and how do these factors interact?
The debate of nature vs. nurture is applicable to many facets of human life,
including the way people think about art. The “taste” theory of
Hume and the “instinct” theory of Conniff represent these different
views.
Scottish philosopher David Hume based his idea of “taste” on the
premises that evaluating art is a learned skill. As Freeland wrote, “Hume
emphasized education and experience: men of taste acquire certain abilities
that lead to agreement about which authors and artworks are the best”
(Freeland 9). Hume acknowledged that individuals have unique preferences, but
was confident that “men of taste” would reach a general consensus
on what good art is. This “standard of taste” is then universal.
He said these cultured men must “preserve minds free from prejudice,”
but also assumed they will reject immorality or excessive violence (Freeland
9). This theory is compatible with his general philosophical view that all human
knowledge is gleaned through the senses.
The theory presented in “The Natural History of Art” by Richard
Conniff places no such emphasis on education or life experience. In fact, his
evolutionary view attributes aesthetic preference to humans’ “innate
propensities,” not inculcated morality. Referring to psychology professor
Richard Coss, he wrote, “Coss made the startling suggestion that we respond
to art, and to our visual world, not just as aesthetes…but as animals”
(Conniff, 95.) Certain characteristics—water, open grassy spaces, scattered
groves of trees, elevation changes, winding trails, bright clearings—are
almost universally preferred in art and in habitat, perhaps harkening back to
our ancestral days on the African savanna.
Understandably, the Hume view and the Conniff view clash occasionally. A nearby
example of this disagreement is Jim Dine’s “Technicolor Heart,”
which is installed on the WSU campus along Stadium Way. When it first appeared
there in 2004, the heart received a large number of negative comments about
it and at least a few attempts at sabotage. From a Conniff instinct perspective,
perhaps this outcry is related to the heart’s location on a grassy open
space. Looking at that space, it has number of the characteristics that are
innately appealing to humans: A clearing-like grassy space with an uphill path
and a few branchy trees. Perhaps those who disliked the heart were responding
to innate indignation that it violated their ideal landscape. In addition, such
bright and startling colors are only present in nature on poisonous creatures
such as the poison dart frog of South America. Student Shawn Wallace perhaps
unknowingly supported this theory in a letter to The Daily Evergreen when he
wrote, “It should have been painted green and stuck between some bushes”
(dailyevergreen.com, Oct. 28, 2004). He might as well have said he wanted the
garish thing to stop disrupting his savanna.
On the other hand, the Hume perspective on the blue heart is represented by
the comments from Keith Wells, the WSU Museum of Art curator. “You should
have some sort of background in art—especially modern art. I really like
the piece, it’s stunning and it has a little bit of everything,”
he was quoted as saying in an Evergreen article. He is trying to imply that
“men of taste” like it so everyone else should like it, too. Art
critics and museum curators are contemporary equivalents to Hume’s educated
men.
Another disagreement between the two theories would arise over the paintings
of Thomas Kinkade. Loathed and maligned by designated art critics, his work
is nonetheless displayed prominently in homes all around the country. From a
Conniff instinct view, Kinkade’s paintings are appealing because he emphasizes
warmth and light in green landscapes, and usually there’s a cozy cottage
appealing to the need for nighttime shelter. Critics dislike his work for being
too pastel, commercialized, and meaningless. Those with knowledge and experience
with art generally have come to the consensus that Kinkade’s painting
are not good art, just as Hume expected they would.
However, the two theories do not always clash because they are not perfect opposites.
For example, the gardens at Versailles appear to fit the evolutionary description
of desirable art, yet they are also admired by experts and contain mythology
references that only the very educated would understand. It makes sense that
the two theories would not always contradict, for even “men of taste”
share a common evolutionary ancestor with the hoi polloi.
The evolutionary theory is simple to understand, even if the influences are
complex. The theory of taste is the intriguing one, especially when considered
from an evolutionary view. Perhaps taste is the acquired ability to overcome
instinctual aesthetic reactions for other qualities deemed important by the
era. For example, it’s doubtful that an infant would be soothed by listening
to an opera solo, yet adults can learn to appreciate it as an art form. On the
darker side, perhaps taste is merely a self-serving construction so those who
attain the status of expert are needed by the ordinary people. The average layman
will typically say he likes an abstruse, experimental film if he thinks he’s
“supposed” to like it. Hume’s “man of taste” emerges
even in small groups of friends, where one is considered the most knowledgeable
about music and the others adopt her preferences as their own.
Though it’s true that neither theory makes sense when considering some
art, it seems the most famous and enduring works of art appeal to both the innate
aesthetic sense and the acquired taste that comes with education. The Mona Lisa,
for example, combines a classic savanna landscape with an enigmatic woman who
tickles our evolutionary curiosity and sympathy. Of course, critics also say
it’s very good for the perspective, technique, and skill. Michelangelo’s
Sistine Chapel speaks to humans’ innate propensity for expansive scenes,
the sky, and a higher being or god. And, of course, it’s remarkably detailed
and a tremendously difficult project that experts appreciate. It seems, then,
that while neither Hume’s nor Conniff’s theory can fully explain
the world of art as we know it today, both humans’ nature and nurture
play a significant role in the way we evaluate art.
===================================