Kant and the Problem of Disinterestedness
According to Kant, fine art follows two paradoxes: it “is a way of presenting that is purposive on its own and that furthers, even though without a purpose, the culture of our mental powers to [facilitate] social communication”(Kant 173) and “it must have the look of nature even though we are conscious of it as art”(Kant 174). In other words, Kant believes that fine art is intentionally produced, yet remains purposive without a purpose, and is fabricated, essentially unnatural, yet must appear natural to its viewers.
Kant’s definition of fine art is based heavily upon his previous deductions
of how beauty is judged in the natural world. He believes that true judgments
of beauty share four characteristics: they are disinterested, universal, necessary,
and purposive without a purpose (Burnham). Since Kant draws a distinction between
rational and aesthetic judgments, he argues that aesthetic judgments are not
based on concepts, or things that can be known, but on intuitions or sensations.
Therefore, a true judgment of beauty is disinterested; it is not based on any
known concept, simply a sensation of unconstrained, completely detached pleasure.
Along these same lines, a beautiful object is purposive, containing the property
or quality of purposefulness, without actually having a concrete purpose. As
Freeland summarizes, Kant believes that “we respond to the object’s
rightness of design, which satisfies our imagination and intellect, even though
we are not evaluating the object’s purpose”(14).
For example, Kant would say that our pleasure in viewing “Starry Night”,
by Vincent Van Gogh, is derived from the harmony and “free play”
of our intuition and understanding that is triggered by the purposiveness of
its forms. There is something aesthetically pleasing about the arrangement of
shapes and blend of colors that causes us pleasure without directly applying
to a concrete or known concept that we may have for how churches should look,
or how the stars should be arranged in the sky. According to Kant, we do not
like “Starry Night” because it contains our favorite color of blue,
or reminds us of the safety and warmth of our hometown. These, he would argue,
are matters of taste and “agreeableness” rather than judgment and
true beauty, and only serve to pollute the disinterestedness that should accompany
our appreciation of the aesthetic.
Kant’s call for disinterestedness in the appreciation of beauty is perhaps
the most irrational part of his theory. Is it humanly possible to be completely
intuitive, to experience something through sensation alone without applying
past experiences or previous knowledge? Can an observer of “Starry Night”
look at the swirls of blue, yellow, and black without attaching the sensation
of movement in the night sky, imitated by the painting, to previous sensations
and experiences of looking up at the stars? Is the judgment of art and beauty
really free from social, political, and cultural factors? Other philosophers
and thinkers like Nietzsche and Freud would argue that art is related to individual
will; Marx would contend that all art, as cultural production, is political
in some sense, and Expressionists, like Van Gogh, would disagree with disinterestedness
by affirming that art is understood in terms of affective response (Burnham).
As a work of fine art, Kant would say that Van Gogh has succeeded in fulfilling
the first paradox of purposefully creating something that has no purpose, or
conceptualizing a non-concept in his painting of “Starry Night”.
Abstract ideas of peace and tranquility are given form, although they are neither
clearly nor conceptually defined. Van Gogh would be considered to possess “genius”
or the “innate mental predisposition (ingenium) through which nature gives
the rule to art”(174), because of his ability to capture an aesthetic
concept and bring it as close as possible to a concrete form. Kant would argue
that Van Gogh was guided by some visceral force to purposefully create “Starry
Night” without committing it to a clear conceptual purpose.
“Starry Night” illustrates the second paradox of appearing natural
despite the fact that it was obviously produced, because the painting is pleasing
without bringing attention to the intentionality of its creation. In this second
paradox, Kant is explaining the aversion that we feel toward art that seems
forced or contrived. We appreciate fine art, he would argue, because it is so
skillfully crafted that we initially conceive of it as if it were something
that simply was. We can later appreciate the technique and style that the artist
has used to create the work, but as an object of aesthetic pleasure, its beauty
is best judged by its form, and not how that form was achieved.
Kant’s theory of fine art and beauty focuses exclusively on those works
that cause pleasure and internal harmony or the “free play” of the
mental faculties. His definition of art is seen as limited by the standards
of today’s art scene, which includes works that are neither beautiful
nor pleasing. However, regardless of Kant’s shortsightedness in excluding
things such as personal interest from the evaluation of art, he succeeds in
providing an in-depth analysis of the reasons why some works evoke our appreciation
and spark our imagination while others do not. His ideas of purposiveness without
a purpose and appearing natural although being produced help to explain why
some works of art seem to please without communicating a specific message or
conveying a direct idea. Although many works of art are clearly intended to
convey a social or political message, like “Guernica” by Picasso,
others, like Van Gogh’s “Starry Night” are simply pleasing
to behold. Kant’s contribution to the field of aesthetic criticism is
significant, regardless of the inability of his theory to encompass everything
that we now define as “art”. As Freeland mentions, “Kant’s
view of beauty had ramifications well into the twentieth century, as critics
emphasized the aesthetic in urging audiences to appreciate new and challenging
artists like Cezanne, Picasso, and Pollock”(15), and his focus on significant
form continues to shape the way we view and justify art.
Works Cited
Freeland, Cynthia. But is it art?. New York: Oxford University Press, 2001.
Kant, Immanuel. Critique of Judgment. Trans. Werner S. Pluhar. Indianapolis:
Hackett
Publishing, 1987.
The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Ed. Douglas Burnham. 2005. Staffordshire
University.
8 Oct. 2005 <http://www.iep.utm.edu/k/kantaest.htm#H2>.
by Tera Ray
Expected Graduation Date: May 2006
Major: English Education
Hometown: Spokane, WA
Kant’s ideas on beauty and disinterestedness in art first captured
my interest when they were discussed by Freeland in the chapter Blood and beauty,
so I decided to take the opportunity to explore them further in this essay.
I checked-out Kant’s Critique of Judgment from the library, and I was
very impressed by the logical structure of his theory. However, I thought that
many of his ideas were necessarily limited by this structure, and I used this
essay to show both the strengths and weaknesses of applying disinterestedness
and “purposiveness without a purpose” to fine art.
Starry Night by Van Gogh
Guernica by Picasso